Top-Rated Free Essay
Preview

Biomedical Ethics

Powerful Essays
2856 Words
Grammar
Grammar
Plagiarism
Plagiarism
Writing
Writing
Score
Score
Biomedical Ethics
Question 1:
This essay revolved around many arguments, but mostly two main pro-life arguments. One includes the argument that it is wrong to kill a human being. A fetus is a human being, therefore it is wrong to kill a fetus. Abortion is the killing of a fetus, therefore abortion is wrong. Another argument involved is the argument that all human beings have a right to life. All fetuses are human beings. Killing a being with a right to life is wrong; therefore it is wrong to kill a fetus. Abortion is the killing of a fetus, therefore abortion is wrong. Through her destructive argument she is attempting to establish that even if the fetus is seen as a human being, it does not automatically have a right to use to body of a woman, and thus does not necessarily have a right to life.
Thomson immediately begins her essay by pointing out the reliance of pro-lifers on the premise that a fetus is a human being from the moment it is conceived. She does not believe this, giving the example that an acorn develops into an oak tree, but that it does not follow that the acorn is an oak tree just as the fetus would be considered a human being. She points out that this is a “slippery-slope argument” and moves on. Thomson broaches on other ideas such as the fetus could be a human being well before birth, and that pro-lifers often focus too much on constructing the argument that a fetus is a human being from conception and little else. Thomson settles with simply granting that the fetus is a human being from the point of conception, and moves on to form an argument. She starts again with a pro-life argument that every person has a right to life, which means the fetus does as well, and although the mother has a right to decide what happens to her body, the fetus’s right to life outweighs this. Thomson admits that this could be plausible, but proceeds to make a case involving a violinist. She develops a scenario where you were kidnapped, and a famous unconscious violinist has been hooked up to you by the Society of Music Lovers in order to save his life. By unplugging him from you, you would kill him, and by remaining hooked up to him for nine months he would survive. Thomson points out that it would be nice to help save his life, but questions your obligation to. She proposes that it could even be longer, such as 9 years or for the rest of your life. Then she brings up that because all persons have a right to life, and violinists are persons, the choice should be obvious. Even though you have a right to decide what happens to your body, the violinist’s right to life outweighs this, and thus you must remain hooked up to the violinist. This leads to her view on the exception of rape. In her example, you were kidnapped, and so you did not have a choice on the matter. Thomson points out that even so, this is unpleasant because “the question of whether you have a right to life at all, or how much of it you have, shouldn’t turn on the question of whether or not you are the product of rape.” (Thomson, 481) Still, Thomson says that people who oppose abortion on these grounds do not mention this or even the case in which the mother has to spend nine months in bed while pregnant. Even if the pregnancy went on for nine years, or even forever, some people would not even make an exception. Thomson points out that this is the mistake, since the right to life is not unproblematic. Thomson then goes on to examine what it is to actually have a right to life. She believes that nobody has a right against you to use part of your body, and that some people believe that the right to life means the right not to be killed. Thomson clarifies this in showing that the violinist may have a right to life, but this does not guarantee having a right to use another person’s body. This shows that the right to life cannot serve pro-lifers very well when developing their argument. Thomson brings up an example where a boy and his small brother are given a box of chocolates and the older boy takes the box and refuses to give his younger brother any of the chocolates, which is unjust seeing how the younger boy was entitled to half or at least some of the chocolates. Because in the violinist case you are not giving him a right to use your body, it would not be unjust to unplug yourself from him. By doing this, Thomson points out you may be doing what he has a right you shall not do, but you are not acting unjustly in doing this. She brings about an idea that “the right to life consists not in the right not to be killed, but rather in the right not to be killed.” (Thomson, 482) This goes back to the issue of abortion and the need for proof that the abortion is unjust killing. Thomson brings up the instance where a woman voluntarily indulges in intercourse, knowing of the chance of pregnancy, and then becomes pregnant. This woman could be seen as responsible for the fetus and human being it will inevitably become. Although this argument has merit, and could show that because the fetus is dependent on the mother and has a right to life, it still does not solve the instance in which an unborn person’s existence is due to rape. Thomson also brings up yet another example where if you open a window to let fresh air in and a burglar comes in that you have given the burglar a right to your house. This is obviously absurd, and Thomson realizes this, but still uses it to get her point across that just because you know something has a possibility of occurring does not mean that you allowed it to happen. Thomson’s constructive argument that to deprive someone of what he has a right to is to treat him unjustly shows that the rape exclusion is not necessary. If a fetus is the result of rape, then according to the belief about unjust killing, they have no right to the use of their mother’s body, and thus aborting them is not unjust killing seeing how they are not being deprived of anything they have a right to. The pro-lifer cannot justify this if they believe that the right to life is the right not to be killed unjustly. They could say that the fetus has a right to life period, but this is again difficult to justify. Going back to what Thomson said earlier, it seems problematic to establish a fetus’s right to life based on whether or not they were the product of rape. What gives the fetus not conceived from rape precedence over the fetus who was conceived from rape? This is where the pro-lifers would have a difficult time justifying any argument, and may even have to provide exceptions to other circumstances, even when not discussing rape. Thomson also points out that there is a difference between something that “ought” to happen and something that needs to happen. She believes that a person can be selfish and callous if they refuse something, such as giving a sibling chocolate, or even allowing a fetus the use of their body. It does not follow, however, that the person is morally required to do such. She brings up the idea of being a “Good Samaritan” and how that is still not enough to justify not having a right to one’s own body. Thomson reiterates a common belief that a mother has a special responsibility for the child, but then counters this by pointing out that we do not have a special responsibility to anyone unless we assume it. If someone does not try to prevent pregnancy or does not attempt to obtain an abortion, then they have assumed responsibility for it. Her final view rests with her belief that abortion is not always permissible, despite her many attempts to prove circumstances in which it is. She believes that there are times where although a woman may have a right to an abortion, it is still indecent and morally wrong to do so. Thomson’s arguments are both convincing. By assuming that the fetus is a person, she sidesteps any argument that would involve the fetus being a person or not, which is smart. Her destructive argument that most pro-lifers believe that if we can prove that a fetus is a person (human being), then it obviously follows that abortion is wrong is false is successful through her use of various examples. Her violinist example showed that the fetus does not necessarily have a right to use your body without your consent. The example involving children and chocolate showed that the boy may be selfish by not giving his brother chocolate, just as the mother may be selfish by getting an abortion, but this doesn’t necessarily make either of them morally wrong. The example involving an open window compared to indulging in intercourse shows that foreseeable, unintended consequences do not always lead to responsibility. These arguments and the rest are all constructed beautifully, and delivered so well that her point is able to be made with ease. Another essay, written by Don Marquis, shows why abortion is immoral. He sets out to show that “abortion is, except in rare cases, seriously immoral”. (Marquis, 475) He bases his argument on the assumption that fetuses have a moral value in the same category of adults. Marquis begins by attempting to explain the wrongness of killing. He states that “the loss of one’s life is one of the greatest losses one can suffer”. (Marquis, 476) By killing someone, he believes that the killing inflicts a great loss of the victim, and this is wrong. He continues by arguing that by being killed one is deprived of all value of their future, and this is the ultimate wrongness of killing. His argument could begin with it is wrong to kill a human being with a valuable future. A fetus is a being with a valuable future, therefore it is wrong to kill a fetus. Abortion is the killing of a fetus, therefore abortion is wrong. Marquis also goes on to compare his argument to the best argument for the wrongness of inflicting pain upon animals. This argument shows that the suffering cause by the infliction of pain is what makes it wrong, and this leads to the conclusion that infliction of pain on animals is wrong. Both this argument and his abortion argument begin with an assumption concerning what it is wrong to do to a person, then look for something that makes the action wrong and recognize this to move on. Because these two structures are the same, Marquis believes that the abortion argument is sound if the animal abuse argument is. He admits that “this argument, if sound, shows only that abortion is prima facie wrong, not that it is wrong in any and all circumstances”. (Marquis, 478) He shows that abortion could be justified if “the loss consequent on failing to abort would be at least as great”. (Marquis, 478) He still believes that the presumption needs to remain that abortion is very seriously wrong. Marquis also touches on the issue of contraception being considered immoral by some. He shows how some argue that contraception could also be argued the same way he argues abortion. In other words, because contraception may be depriving future lives and thus future value, it must be wrong. Marquis shows this is not exactly true though. He states that it is not the same because “there is no non-arbitrarily identifiable subject of the loss in the case of contraception”. (Marquis, 476) He concludes his argument by stating his purpose of setting out an argument for the serious presumptive wrongness of abortion subject to the assumption that the moral permissibility of abortion stands or falls on the moral status of the fetus”. (Marquis, 476) He finishes with his thought that it is wrong to kill adult human beings, and it is not wrong to end the life of some arbitrarily chosen single human cell. Since fetuses can be seen as either of these, he proposes that there is a new problem that can be solved, but only once the fetal property is solved. Although Marquis has some good points, one could object to his argument by questioning if it is permissible to kill someone who does not have a valuable future, such as a lazy person, or a prostitute, and so on. It seems to follow from his argument that it is okay to kill a person like this. He would respond that yes it is permissible to kill beings without a valuable future, which is problematic because who is to say who has a valuable future? One could question if his argument was a subjective notion or an objective one, and ultimately there would need to be a hybrid of subjective and objective. Marquis would probably respond to the violinist case by saying it would be wrong to kill the violinist because he obviously has a valuable future if he is able to survive. He is a famous violinist, which presumably means he is wealthy and good at the violin. Even simply focusing on his profession as a violinist, it is obvious that he has a valuable future and thus it would be wrong to unplug him and kill him. One could argue that that is only letting him die, but ultimately the point would be that by unplugging him you are taking his chance of life and a valuable future away from him, which is wrong. This response would probably help the success of his argument by providing another example to support.
Require the
Question 2: In our society, it definitely seems obvious that we want randomized clinical trials. They are beneficial when attempting to discover the solution to a medical problem or mystery, and are overall a helpful way to change therapeutic methods. Despite these benefits, according to Hellman and Hellman, randomized clinical trials are controversial due to the fact that “researchers participating in such studies are required to modify their ethical commitments to individual patients and do serious damage to the concept of the physician as a practicing, empathetic professional who is primarily concerned with each patient as an individual”. (Hellman and Hellman, 260)
Theoretical equipoise is present when evidence related to two different treatments is exactly balanced. The motivation for equipoise in the first place is to conceive of equipoise in a way that preserves a physician’s moral integrity and allow for good science. One would see this as necessary due to the fact that the patient’s best interests should always be put first with no exceptions, even when science is involved. Of course, this is not plausible due to the fact that the physician is forced to play two roles: a physician who acts in the best interests of the patient, and a scientist who is only concerned with answering scientific questions.
Freedman proposed another type of equipoise in response to this to show that individual views are not what determine the justification of a clinical trial. This type, known as clinical equipoise, is present if and only if there would be disagreement in the clinical community that is concerning the relative efficiency of the two trial arms. This is different from theoretical equipoise in that it occurs when the views of the community are balanced rather than only the physician. Clinical equipoise does not satisfy the moral foundation of acting in the patients best interest at all times, which could make it seem unworkable. Even so, one could say that the physician is not acting in a way that the clinical community would say falls below the patient’s best interest. This means that the original foundation of equipoise (acting in the patient’s best interest) would be lost. Although we could reject equipoise altogether, then we are back to square one in a sense and need other ways to satisfy what the physicians were attempting to do with the randomized clinical trials.
Hellman and Hellman believe that the moral foundation for clinical equipoise is definitely important, and should be taken seriously. They believe that “surely, other techniques can be developed to deal with both observer bias and patient selection” (Hellman and Hellman, 263) such as “matched pair analysis”. They still admit that their discussion of alternatives is “sketchy and incomplete”. (Hellman and Hellman, 263) They do not want to continue randomized clinical trials seeing how they pose such ethical dilemmas that must be dealt with by the physician/scientist. In concluding their essay, they urge readers to “develop and use alternative methods for acquiring clinical knowledge”. (Hellman and Hellman, 263)

You May Also Find These Documents Helpful

  • Good Essays

    Thomson Handout 1

    • 951 Words
    • 3 Pages

    The standard argument that Thomson is making I that a fetus is a human from the moment it is conceived. That people say to view how humans are made in which includes the process of conception that is said to be human then it must be true.…

    • 951 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Thomson made her assumptions very clear through the different situations she gave to when abortion can be justified. She proves the moral permissibility to abort a fetus in three different scenarios and gave reasons to why abortion is never immoral. Under certain circumstances, despite all situation not being unjust, many still question the ethical principles behind abortion. Although everyone is given the 'right to life', morally it would be unaccepted to force others to carry on a life they do not want in their body. For example, going back to the violinist. If the innocent person is forced to help safe the violinist, it goes against her autonomy and one moral principle should not outweigh…

    • 622 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    Thomson’s argument is that abortion of a fetus that is not viable (viable meaning that it is at a stage of development…

    • 1366 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Good Essays

    In her article Thomson starts off by giving antiabortionists the benefit of the doubt that fetuses are human persons. She adds that all persons have the right to life and that it is wrong to kill any person. Also she states that someone's right to life is stronger than another person's autonomy and that the only conflict with a fetuses right to life is a mother's right to autonomy. Thus the premises make abortion impermissible. Then Thomson precedes to attacks the premise that one's right to autonomy can be more important to another's right to life in certain situations. She uses quite an imaginative story to display her point of view. Basically there is a hypothetical situation in which a very famous violinist is dying. Apparently the only way for the violinist to survive is to be "plugged" into a particular woman, in which he could use her kidneys to continue living. The catch is that the Society of Music Lovers kidnapped this woman in the middle of the night in order to obtain the use of her kidneys. She then woke up and found herself connected to an unconscious violinist. This obviously very closely resembles an unwanted pregnancy. It is assumed that the woman unplugging herself is permissible even though it would kill the…

    • 1125 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    goodwill

    • 1161 Words
    • 5 Pages

    You are asked to imagine a famous violinist falling into a coma. The society of music lovers determines from medical records that you and you alone can save the violinist's life by being hooked up to him for nine months. The music lovers break into your home while you are asleep and hook the unconscious (and unknowing, hence innocent) violinist to you. You may want to unhook him, but you are then faced with this argument put forward by the music lovers: The violinist is an innocent person with a right to life. Unhooking him will result in his death. Therefore, unhooking him is morally wrong.…

    • 1161 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Thomson Abortion

    • 860 Words
    • 4 Pages

    One of the biggest moral issue today is woman's rights with abortion. Many people argued for the rights to keep abortion while others argued for banning it. In the article "The Rights of a Woman Do Not Outweigh the Rights of A Child" by Judith Jarvis Thomson, who is a philosopher and invented an analogy for her debate, talks about how a child has more right than the mother in the case of abortion and that abortion is the same thing as "killing" , Thomson says. Thomson claims the idea that anyone can argue that all abortion is impermissible. The article "Abortions Should Be Restricted to Before Twenty Weeks Gestation" by Douglas Johnson who is…

    • 860 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    The author writes about her view on abortion. It defends abortion rights on women's right to control their own bodies and health conditions, rather than denying the personhood of the fetus.…

    • 242 Words
    • 1 Page
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    Abortion is Morally Wrong

    • 1320 Words
    • 6 Pages

    In the mid-1800s states started to pass laws making it illegal to carry out an abortion. The motivations for anti-abortion laws varied from state to state. One of the reasons included fears that the population would be dominated by the children of newly arriving immigrants, whose birth rates were higher than those of "native" Anglo-Saxon women. The real issue at hand regarding the abortion debate is not the women's rights or other factors but the status of the unborn fetus. Participants of the personal choice argument suggest that the unborn fetus is not a human being, but if the unborn child is indeed a human person, then no amount of freedom justifies its elective termination. Therefore prochoice debaters has made an argument stating the question by presupposing their conclusions, they are only plausible if and only if the unborn are not human persons.…

    • 1320 Words
    • 6 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Better Essays

    In On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion, Mary Anne Warren discusses a few arguments against abortion, namely bringing into play whether the fetus is actually a person, or “not a member of the moral community”. She…

    • 1122 Words
    • 5 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Good Essays

    Judith Thomson article simply outlines the right of abortion with women. Judith presents the argument that everyone has a right to life. However, throughout the article she underlines key arguments and give multiple examples and analogies to further prove her point. Thomson began by saying that because everyone has a right to life, it is automatically assumed that the fetus is a person, and therefore has a right to life. Furthermore, the mother does have a right and say so to what she wants to happen to her body, however, it is argued that a person's right to life is stronger than a mother's right to decide what happens to her body, concluding that the fetus may not be killed and an abortion cannot be performed. Judith gives the other side of the argument throughout the article and picks up all the flaws of the main argument that everyone makes.…

    • 1583 Words
    • 7 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Abortion Reading Task

    • 991 Words
    • 4 Pages

    The writer begins by arguing that a lot of debates on the topic of abortion seem to think of the woman in question as just a container for the foetus, and the foetus in often the main focus of the debate. Kolbert argues that great consideration needs to be given to the woman’s rights and needs as well as those of the foetus.…

    • 991 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Good Essays

    Over the last several decades, the topic of abortion has become an increasingly controversial and heated argument in popular culture, press, and medical fields. The process of the abortion as defined by Meriam-Webster is “the deliberate termination of a human pregnancy, resulting in death of the embryo or fetus”. This process has been thoroughly discussed in a number of fields ranging from medical ethics to Christian journalism, in which it has both been defended and attacked. The main focus of the controversy seems to be determining at what point a fetus is considered a human being and therefore at what point abortion becomes murder. Some argue this occurs at the moment of conception while others believe this does not argue until the fetus develops fingers and vital organs around the tenth week of pregnancy. Some, such as medical ethics author Judith Jarvis Thompson, take a different stance all together and argue that drawing a line between being considered a person and not a person is an illogical argument without purpose. Thompson claims that calling a fetus at the moment of conception a human is like calling a freshly fallen acorn an oak tree, however, she does agree that the transition from fetus to human being occurs a long time before birth.…

    • 1141 Words
    • 3 Pages
    Good Essays
  • Better Essays

    Violinist Theory

    • 1475 Words
    • 4 Pages

    Throughout the class we have opened our minds to three different views on abortions. After reading and understanding each philosopher’s argument I agree with Thomson. Unlike Marquis who argues that most abortions are wrong because it deprives a fetus of its future, and Warren who states that abortions are permissible because a fetus is not a person; Thomson believes that abortions are permissible under normal circumstances because a woman has a right to stop something from using her body against her own will. We will look at Thomson’s argument compared to Marquis to prove that Thomson is correct that abortions are morally permissible under normal circumstances. After we will compare Thomson with Warren to prove that even though Thomson supports that abortions are permissible under normal circumstances that abortions are not permissible under all circumstances. When we compare Thomson and Marquis we will look at Thomson’s Violinist case.…

    • 1475 Words
    • 4 Pages
    Better Essays
  • Powerful Essays

    Pros And Cons Of Abortion

    • 2060 Words
    • 9 Pages

    An argument first presented by Judith Jarvis Thomson states that even if the fetus has a right to life, abortion is morally permissible because a woman has a right to control her own body. Thomson's variant of this argument draws an analogy between forcing a woman to continue an unwanted pregnancy and forcing a person's body to be used as a dialysis machine for another person suffering from kidney failure. It is argued that just as it would be permissible to "unplug" and thereby cause the death of the person who is using one's…

    • 2060 Words
    • 9 Pages
    Powerful Essays
  • Better Essays

    Abortions To Kill

    • 1601 Words
    • 7 Pages

    Abortion, known to make lives easier and support stem cell research, masks its true identity of murder with such interests since it justifies the inexistence of a person’s life with those societal pleasures. With that in mind, society must demolish masked murder because life, the most important aspect. must be maintained to secure future lives. In fact, individuals find abortion to exist as murder because an embryo presents a form of human life. As a result, they condemn stem cell research that requires abortions. In contrast, others argue that interests like stem cell research, population conservation and financial convenience justify abortion. They also believe that an embryo consists of a woman’s body. To clarify, an embryo develops at…

    • 1601 Words
    • 7 Pages
    Better Essays